Attempted Refutation of the
possibility of the god described in traditional monotheism
using several reductiones ad absurdum
Comments welcomed as to whether this works or not.
Introduction
The monotheisms of Christianity, Judaism and Islam all claim
that there is a being that is eternal, immaterial, infinite in
presence, omniscient, omnipotent, perfect and (as a bonus) benevolent
and who is the greatest being possible such that it is "that
than which nothing greater can be thought" [1].
This being is given the name God, a word that is almost universally
accepted as perfectly synonymous with the above mentioned attributes.
This definition of "God" will be adopted here for
purposes of analysis of some of the claims of theism. When the
word God is written it will be understood to refer to the boundless,
perfect and benevolent being described by monotheisms, and not
to the idea of a divinity in general (for example a Greek or
Egyptian God), which in many cases is little better than a mortal.
The several reductiones ad absurdum to follow will
show that such a god - that is, a necessary (eternal) , non-physical
(immaterial), plenistic (everywhere
& infinite in presence), almighty (omniscient & omnipotent)
[2], perfect
(symmetrical) and good (benevolent) being - is impossible both
metaphysically and physically, and that only finite contingent beings
are possible (such beings being readily observable and well known
facts about the world).
The subsequent argumentation is offered in the spirit of that
which Guanillo once offered his refutation St Anselm's Ontological
Argument for the Existence of God, by replying to him under the
guise of a fool. St Anselm (1033-1109) as everyone will recall,
was "the outstanding Christian philosopher and theologian
of the eleventh century", where as Guanillo was the outstanding
Fool of the same period. For more on this fascinating exchange
visit the Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy article on St Anselm and his Ontological
Argument.
Negation 1
Proposition N1: There is a being, God, who is an almighty, necessary
being "that than which nothing greater can be thought" (St
Anselm, ).
Reductio 1:
- There is an almighty necessary being who is the greatest
being possible
- An almighty being can do absolutely anything [definition
of almightiness]
- An almighty being can cause itself to cease existing [an
example of almightiness]
- Necessary beings are uncaused and exist eternally without
beginning or end [definition of necessary being]
- Therefore, there are no almighty, necessary beings [contradiction
of premise 3 by premise 4]
Reductio 1 shows that God cannot be both an almighty and a
necessary being since these attributes cannot coherently co-exist
because, as seen, they lead to a contradiction. The existential
condition (or "existential nature”) necessary existence and
the predicate almighty are mutually exclusive. An object
that embodies an existential nature of necessary existence is
prohibited a priori from ever possessing the attribute
of almightiness.
Reductio 1 shows that Proposition N1 is false. That is to say
that a being that is both almighty and necessary
is metaphysically (logically) impossible, from which it follows
that such a being is also physically impossible. But this is
all that N1 confirms explicitly and it does not deny the possibility
of either a necessary non-almighty being, or a contingent almighty
being.
Reductio 1 in fact apparently allows that the greatest being
possible, "that than which no greater can be thought" (which
, a posteriori, must necessarily exist, since beings
are observable facts and therefore there is logically a "greatest" among
them), could in fact be a necessary being or an almighty
being but not both.
However, on closer inspection Reductio 1 implicitly shows
that almighty beings per se are absolutely impossible, irrespective
of their existential nature (which in this case is "necessarily
existent"), since, irrespective of whether or not the being
is necessary or contingent, it can do nothing about its existential
condition, since doing so is a priori prohibited. That
is, it is a priori true that a necessary being must for
eternity be a necessary being and can never be at any time
contingent -since to be contingent means that it will have to
have begun to exist at sometime or other, which is in contradistinction
to existing necessarily, always, without beginning or end. And
also the converse is true; that is, it is a priori true
that a contingent being can never become a necessary being, since
having the existential nature "contingently existent" it
at one time began to exist and therefore has not existed always.
Nonetheless, the impossibility of almighty beings is only implicit in
Reductio 1, since the reductio only explicitly shows, the impossibility
of both necessary existence and almightiness simultaneously pertaining
to, and predicating, a being, respectively. It says nothing about
the possibility of necessary beings lacking almightiness existing,
in which case it is initially conceivable that necessary beings
are possible. And it says nothing, apparently, about almighty
beings being possible, provided that they also do not embody
necessary existence.
To show incontrovertibly that almighty beings are impossible
requires showing that either necessary beings are the only beings
possible, in which case Reductio 1 would show that almighty beings
are impossible (because necessary beings cannot be almighty);
or that, if necessary being is impossible, then the converse
of necessary being – that is, contingent being – can
(incorrectly it will turn out) be predicated by almightiness.
Some analysis of the possibility of necessary being is helpful.
Affirmation 1
Logical possibility of necessary being
Proposition A1: Necessary existence is logically possible
- Necessary existence is logically possible
- A necessary being is uncaused and exists eternally without
beginning or end [definition of necessary being]
- Premise 2 is a priori logically coherent [no internal
contradictions]
- Therefore necessary existence is logically possible
Affirmation 2
Physical possibility of necessary existence
Proposition A 2: Necessary existence is physically possible
- Necessary existence is physically possible
- Something beginning to exist where before there was
nothing cannot be explained [contingent
existence] [4]
- Anything existing always cannot be explained [necessary existence]
- There is no reason to assert that either premise 2 or premise
3 are true or false, or that one is more probable than the
other, since both must, in the absence of evidence, be considered
to be a priori equally likely states of reality and
further, both must be considered to be equally a priori inexplicable.
[That is, no good reason can be given as to why anything should
begin to exist (premise 2) except that it is impossible for
something to exist always; and equally, no good reason can
be given as to why anything should exist always without beginning
or end (premise 3) except that no-thing can begin to
exist and that therefore, given that things exists, these things
have existed always. This "symmetry of inexplicability" and
mutual exclusivity suggests that neither of these possible
states of reality can be ruled out as descriptions of reality,
and that therefore both must be held to be physically possible.]
- Therefore both necessary existence and contingent existence
are physically possible states of reality.
Summary 1
Affirmations 1 & 2, though they do not explicitly demonstrate
the physical reality of necessary existence, do show the
logical and physical possibility of it. That is, neither
necessary existence nor contingent existence can be shown to
be logically and physically true descriptions of current reality,
but equally, neither can they be shown to be logically and physically
impossible descriptions.
Therefore, as there is no inherent logical or physical inconsistency
in assuming the possibility of necessary being, it is therefore
coherent to hold that necessary being is logically and physically
possible.
Synthesis 1
Affirmation 1 shows that necessary existence is logically possible.
Combining affirmation 1 with negation 1 it follows that if necessary
beings are the only beings possible, then almighty beings are
impossible.
However, Affirmation 1 also shows that contingent existence
is possible (which is also an observable fact) which opens up
the (absurd) possibility that such beings can be predicated
by almightiness.
To formally rule out the absurdity of almighty contingent beings
it is perhaps only sufficient to note the contradiction in the
term “almighty contingent being”. Nevertheless, Negation
2 will demonstrate this intuitively obvious fact rigorously.
Negation 2 will explicitly show what is already implicit in
Negation 1: that almighty contingent beings are impossible.
Negation 2
Proposition N2: there are beings that are both almighty and contingent.
(Note: Negation 1 precludes the simultaneous realisation
of both almightiness and necessary existence in the same being,
leaving only one logical existential alternative nature to accompany
the predicate "almighty, and that is contingency).
Reductio 2:
- There are almighty contingent beings
- An almighty being can do absolutely anything [definition
of almightiness]
- A contingent being will have begun to exist and may cease
to exist at sometime [definition of contingency]
- A necessary being is uncaused and exists eternally without
beginning or end [definition of necessary being]
- An almighty being that is contingent can, on premise 2, cause
itself to become necessary
- It follows that there are no almighty contingent beings [contradiction
of premise 5 using premises 3 and 4, rendering premise 1 absurd]
Clearly, a being that is contingent can never become necessary.
Therefore proposition N2 is false. There are no almighty, contingent
beings.
Notes:
The conclusion (6) in Reductio 2 is true irrespective of
whether there are necessary beings, as might be well be the case.
Premise 5 is clearly false, but there is even some doubt as
to whether the proposition it represents is in fact meaningful
and sufficiently internally consistent as to serve as a premise
in a reductio. It seems meaningless
not to mention absurd to say that something that is contingent
can become necessary. Indeed, "Reductio 2" is trivial
and cannot even command respect as a well formed argument.
Now that almightiness as a predicate of any being,
whether of necessary or contingent nature, has been shown to
be impossible it can, without concern, be removed from the illustrious
list of attributes supposedly possessed by God.
On the above arguments using reductio ad absurdum, it is true
that almighty beings of any existential description, whether
necessary or contingent, are impossible.
Nonetheless it would be interesting to continue further and
to explore other possible existential and predicate conditions
of being. Doing so will expose why theologians have claimed that
God is an infinite, almighty necessary being.
Negation 3
Proposition N3: There are necessary, finite beings
Finite is used to convey limited power, or non-almightiness,
as well as spatial and, especially, temporal limitedness and is a convenient
antonym of almighty. Feeble will
be used to convey limited power but not limited extension or duration; that is, a feeble being (on this definition) can exist everywhere and eternally but is not almighty .
It should be immediately apparent, even without embarking on
what will prove to be another trivial as well as questionable reductio, that
the proposition "there are necessary finite beings" is
internally inconsistent. However:
Reductio 3:
- There are finite necessary beings
- A finite being cannot do all and any thing,
or exist everywhere or exist eternally [definition of finite
being]
- A necessary being is uncaused and exists eternally without
beginning or end [definition of necessary being]
- Existing eternally is non-finite
- Therefore there are no finite necessary beings. [Premise
4 shows that necessary being (premise 3) involves infinitude,
which conflicts with premise 2, rendering premise 1 incoherent;
that is, absurd]
To be finite and necessary is inconsistent since one contradicts
the other.
Therefore proposition N3 is false. There are no necessary, finite
beings.
To see if there are any feeble necessary beings:
Proposition N3a: There are necessary, finite beings
Reductio 3a
- There are feeble necessary beings
- A feeble being cannot do all and any thing,
but can, as part of its existential nature, exist everywhere and/or exist eternally [definition of feeble
being]
- A necessary being is uncaused and exists eternally without
beginning or end [definition of necessary being]
- Therefore, feeble necessary beings are possible [there is no inconsistency between premises 2 and 3 and moreover premise 3 is implicit in premise 2, rendering premise 1 coherent].
These negations seem somewhat unnecessary and needlessly harsh
on theism, since N3 denies the possibility of
a necessary being that is in every way finite (which is intuitively obvious); and N3a allows only the
possibility of a necessary being that is simply feeble - that is, it is limited in power and can only exist eternally if it already happens to exist eternally (it has no choice in the matter and in that sense it is truly a sorry and feeble being).
Together with Negation 1, which
denies the simultaneous realisation of the predicate almightiness (infinitude in all respects) and the existential nature necessary
being , there is no possible accommodation for God to be a necessary
being of any sort other than a feeble necessary being (that is, limited
in power but not in duration or extension). The possibility of a necessary being that is either infinite or finite is utterly denied.
Finally, some trivial exercises in showing that finite contingent beings are possible. First the logical argument
Affirmation 3 (using deduction)
Proposition A3: Finite contingent beings are logically possible
- Finite, contingent beings are logically possible
- A finite being cannot do all and any thing, or exist
everywhere or exist eternally but it can do some things [definition of finite being]
- A contingent being will have begun to exist and will cease
to exist at sometime [definition of contingency]
- Therefore, finite contingent beings are logically possible. [no contradiction
among any of the premises]
Affirmation 4 (using induction)
Proposition A4: Finite contingent beings are physically possible
- Finite contingent beings are physically possible
- Finite beings exist [fact 1, observational]
- Contingency is evident in the beings and things that exist [fact 2, observational]
- Therefore, finite contingent beings are physically possible.
This last affirmation, together with Reductio 3a demonstrate the obvious, observationally verifiable fact that apart from the
as yet undetermined question of the spatial, temporal and causal
finitude or infinitude of the universe itself, the only kinds
of beings that are both logically and physically possible and which may possess causal powers,
are either finite and contingent or necessary but feeble.
Summary and conclusions
It turns out that, contrary to the claims of theism, the being
identified as God, cannot exist and could not possibly
possess all the attributes and natures outlined in the introduction.
Specifically the above arguments show that:
"God" can be necessary but not almighty (Reductio
1, Affirmations 1 & 2), which from Reductio 3a turns out to be in fact "necessary and feeble".
"God" can be contingent, but not almighty (which as it turns out is also Richard Swinburne's thesis)
And that under no circumstance (i.e. not for any existential nature) can there be almighty beings.
It is clear from this that God in the sense intended by the Anselmian perfect being theology adopted by monotheistic
religions is an impossible being. This accounts for the quotation
marks around the word God above, since the beings so mentioned can no longer be identified
with the god of monotheism.
Negation 1 clearly shows the impossibility of both almightiness
and necessary being inhering in the same being. And Reductio
3 shows the impossibility of finiteness and necessary being.
The only possible necessary beings are demonstrated by Reductio 3a, and those are the feeble beings that are causally limited though they may not be spatially or temporally limited (Not withstanding the Universe
itself which may be either spatially or temporally infinite
or both, but which strictly speaking is not a being in the sense of possessing willful causal powers unless we consider the thesis that our consciousness and hat of any other possible being counts as the universe become conscious).
Notes
The negations and affirmations have taken into account the physical aspects to the arguments
though, in fact, they needn't have. This follows from the fact
of the claim of the monotheism’s that God is an immaterial
entity, and therefore it would have been sufficient to have simply
considered logical possibilities of necessary being. However,
since the Universe itself is a “being” or in fact the being (a verb, as in something existing, being, persisting and so on and not
a being, or this or that being) physical possibility of necessary
being was considered.
There is a tendency even among scientists to conflate the concept
of God as set out by the monotheisms with the idea of a "deity"
that can be identified as being the laws of nature, a kind of
folkish Hegelianism. This idea can and should be rejected on
two grounds. First, it is just one more preposterous hypothesis
that explains nothing, and is in fact preposterous because it
explains nothing. And second because it strips away the essential
attributes of God that form the pillars of monotheisms' conceptualisation
of him - intelligence, personhood, will and benevolence. Though
there are good grounds for rejecting all of these anyway, not to mention
the fundamental idea of God to which they relate in any way, any
discussion of monotheism’s conceptualisation of god,
or even that of theism's in general, must deal with the genuine
article so to speak, and not some relativistic substitute such
as the Laws of Nature or the fact of "human progress" as
in Hegel's dialectical system.